Epistemic closure
Epistemic closure[1] is a property of some belief systems. It is the principle that if a subject knows , and knows that entails , then can thereby come to know . Most epistemological theories involve a closure principle and many skeptical arguments assume a closure principle.
On the other hand, some epistemologists, including Robert Nozick, have denied closure principles on the basis of reliabilist accounts of knowledge. Nozick, in Philosophical Explanations, advocated that, when considering the Gettier problem, the least counter-intuitive assumption we give up should be epistemic closure. Nozick suggested a "truth tracking" theory of knowledge, in which the x was said to know P if x's belief in P tracked the truth of P through the relevant modal scenarios.[2]
A subject may not actually believe q, for example, regardless of whether he or she is justified or warranted. Thus, one might instead say that knowledge is closed under known deduction: if, while knowing p, S believes q because S knows that p entails q, then S knows q.[1] An even stronger formulation would be as such: If, while knowing various propositions, S believes p because S knows that these propositions entail p, then S knows p.[1] While the principle of epistemic closure is generally regarded as intuitive,[3] philosophers such as Robert Nozick and Fred Dretske have argued against it.
Epistemic closure and skeptical arguments
The epistemic closure principle typically takes the form of a modus ponens argument:
- S knows that p.
- S knows that p entails q.
- Therefore, S knows q.
This epistemic closure principle is central to many versions of skeptical arguments. A skeptical argument of this type will involve knowledge of some piece of widely accepted information to be knowledge, which will then be pointed out to entail knowledge of some skeptical scenario, such as the brain in a vat scenario or the cartesian evil demon scenario. A skeptic might say, for example, that if you know that you have hands, then you know that you are not a handless brain in a vat (because knowledge that you have hands implies that you know you are not handless, and if you know that you are not handless, then you know that you are not a handless brain in a vat).[4] The skeptic will then utilize this conditional to form a modus tollens argument. For example, the skeptic might make an argument like the following:
- You do not know that you are not a handless brain in a vat (~K(~h))
- If you know that you have hands, then you know that you are not a handless brain in a vat (K(o) → K(~h))
- Conclusion: Therefore, you do not know that you have hands (~K(o))
Much of the epistemological discussion surrounding this type of skeptical argument involves whether to accept or deny the conclusion, and how to do each. Ernest Sosa says that there are three possibilities in responding to the skeptic:
- Agree with the skeptic by granting him both premises and the conclusion (1, 2, c)
- Disagree with the skeptic by denying premise 2 and the conclusion, but maintaining premise 1 (1, ~2, ~c) as Nozick and Dretske do. This amounts to denying the epistemic closure principle.
- Disagree with the skeptic by denying premise 1 and the conclusion, but maintaining premise 2 (~1, 2, ~c) as Moore does. This amounts to maintaining the epistemic closure principle, and holding that knowledge is closed under known implication.
Justificatory closure
In the seminal 1963 paper, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Edmund Gettier gave an assumption (later called the “principle of deducibility for justification” by Irving Thalberg, Jr.)[5] that would serve as a basis for the rest of his piece: “for any proposition P, if S is justified in believing P and P entails Q, and S deduces Q from P and accepts Q as a result of this deduction, then S is justified in believing Q.”[6] This was seized upon by Thalberg, who rejected the principle in order to demonstrate that one of Gettier's examples fails to support Gettier's main thesis that justified true belief is not knowledge (in the following quotation, (1) refers to “Jones will get the job”, (2) refers to “Jones has ten coins”, and (3) is the logical conjunction of (1) and (2)):
Why doesn't Gettier's principle (PDJ) hold in the evidential situation he has described? You multiply your risks of being wrong when you believe a conjunction. [… T]he most elementary theory of probability indicates that Smith's prospects of being right on both (1) and (2), namely, of being right on (3), are bound to be less favorable than his prospects of being right on either (1) or (2). In fact, Smith's chances of being right on (3) might not come up to the minimum standard of justification which (1) and (2) barely satisfy, and Smith would be unjustified in accepting (3). (Thalberg 1969, p. 798)
Epistemic closure in U.S. political discussion
The term "epistemic closure" has been used in U.S. political debate to refer to the claim that political belief systems can be closed systems of deduction, unaffected by empirical evidence.[7] This use of the term was popularized by libertarian blogger and commentator Julian Sanchez in 2010 as an extreme form of confirmation bias.[7][8]
See also
- False-consensus effect
- Confirmation bias
- Truthiness
- Echo chamber (media)
- Closure: A Short History of Everything by Hilary Lawson, Routledge 2001
References
- 1 2 3 Luper, Steven (31 December 2001). "The Epistemic Closure Principle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ↑ Philosophical explanations, By Robert Nozick (Harvard 1981), page 204
- ↑ Brady, Michael; Pritchard, Duncan (2005). "Epistemological Contextualism: Problems and Prospects". The Philosophical Quarterly. 55 (219): 161–171. doi:10.1111/j.0031-8094.2005.00393.x.
- ↑ Sosa, Ernest (1999-10-01). "How to Defeat Opposition to Moore". Noûs. 33: 141–153. doi:10.1111/0029-4624.33.s13.7. ISSN 1468-0068.
- ↑ Thalberg Jr., Irving (November 1969). "In Defense of Justified True Belief". Journal of Philosophy. 66 (22): 794–803. JSTOR 2024370.
- ↑ Gettier, Edmund (June 1963). "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?". Analysis. 23 (6): 121–3. doi:10.1093/analys/23.6.121. JSTOR 3326922.
- 1 2 Patricia Cohen (27 April 2010). "'Epistemic Closure'? Those are Fighting Words". The New York Times. Retrieved 28 November 2012.
- ↑ Sanchez, Julian (26 March 2010). "Frum, Cocktail Parties, and the Threat of Doubt".
External links
- "The Epistemic Closure Principle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Epistemic closure at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- "Epistemic closure". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Epistemic closure at PhilPapers